First, "evil" doesn't truly exist. It is not a force in the universe.
It is a valuation of behavior and phenomena. In the absence of
subjective experience that valuation does not exist. It may also be that a subjective concept of fairness cannot exist in the absence of
social drives.
(I suspect this is true but I'm not prepared to make such a claim in absolute terms. Comments are welcomed.) As a result, what we perceive as 'wrong-doing' wouldn't be perceived as
wrong without social instincts or culturally learned social norms
(which stem from social instincts). If somehow we managed to be social
creatures in a world where harm were not possible we probably couldn't
conceive of wrong-doing or evil as no action could result in
consequences worse than lost opportunity. Evil is merely a shorthand
for behavior and phenomena that offend our desires for fairness and
freedom from harm.
Second, in a theological god model, we
need to separately consider (a) the creation of a world which allows evil (harm and
unfairness) from (b) other actions by that god that we might perceive as
unfair or harmful.
a. Should we hold the god accountable for harm that
results from creation of a harm-enabled environment? For example, if
someone were to put broken glass in a playpen and also put a baby in the
playpen can we blame them for the cuts the baby will almost inevitably
receive? It may seem a straw man argument in that the baby lacks awareness
necessary for alleged free will, but (1) real babies are really harmed
in our real world and (2) and even as aware adults our awareness is
never complete; thus we are susceptible to harm we can't be adequately aware of.
b. Additionally, a theological god is 'at work' in people's lives. And if
in our material world wherein we cooperate and compete for resources,
is it possible for such a god to tip the scales in any one person's
favor without tipping in a less favorable way for other people? There
may be exceptions but generally the answer is: no. If we are to assume
God had a hand in David's victory over Goliath it shouldn't be hard to
see that from Goliath's perspective (and that of the Philistines) God's intervention was evil (unfair and harmful). Who created that evil?
Third,
let's not overlook natural evil. I think we can generally agree that
animals are capable of experiencing pain. (They have nervous systems.
If they didn't they would suffer the same consequences as congenital
analgesia patients.) Most animals die painfully... to predation,
disease, trauma. Natural disasters produce massive concentrations of
suffering to humans and other animals. And, "Most accidents happen in
the home." Were we placed in a world created for us yet is obviously
out to get us? It might be argued that harm has benefits. And it's
somewhat true, in a tautological way. When we get hurt we learn to
value freedom from harm. But if the world weren't harmful we wouldn't
need this lesson.
Fourth, did the god create the animals? With
varying degrees of denial of a natural bio-genesis and evolution we have
to consider where these animals came from?
(from: God's Parasites )
Fifth,
does (or will) evil 'exist' in Heaven? If not then how can all the
reasons evil is necessary on Earth suddenly become unnecessary in that
change of venue? There are arguments (rationalizations actually) for why we might 'need' to
experience a temporary world of suffering before we experience an
eternal world without suffering. But these postulates really don't hold
water, especially considering the vast range in both duration and
quality of life we experience. How long does a baby, child or young
adult need to live before they've met the heavenly prerequisite? How
much must they suffer first? The whole concept of this life being
a necessary evil as a stepping stone to a perfect afterlife is intellectually
bankrupt. And if it is true that good is not possible without the presence or potential for bad, it doesn't bode well for the ultimate good of Heaven. (I half expect someone to claim that the "bad" of Hell allows for the "good" of Heaven, or some special case pleading for Heaven/God. Feel free to preemptively counter one of these claims in comments.)
The
argument that the possibility of evil is necessary for the existence of
freewill is largely meaningless unless you can make a decent case for
the existence of freewill. Arguments that are made for the existence of
freewill are unconvincing on an objective level. Arguments that
freewill is in illusion are increasingly consistent with demonstrable
facts as science continues to improve our understanding of
neurophysiology. It would be irresponsible of me to claim this matter
has been resolved. But as our knowledge increases,
the presupposition of freewill unravels.
Some believe that good vs. evil is about picking sides, choosing to be on the side of good. In the
sense that behavior that is 'good' is behavior that is beneficial to
something (perhaps humanity or some part of it) and behavior that is
'evil' is harmful to something (perhaps humanity, perhaps a fly that has
just had it's wings removed) you're either acting in our (humanity's) favor or
against it. (I would argue that even in the example of torturing flies, humanity is harmed even if it's only morally, philosophically or on some academic level.) But no one is going 'pick a side' and strive to do 'evil'
at every possible opportunity. Likewise, those who consciously choose
to pick the good side are going to make choices along the way that will
do more harm than good, knowingly or otherwise. Sure, you can pick a
side, but it's merely an abstract and unrealizable ideal. It might be
better to realize that as humanity, and life in general, are going to
outlast you, your greater responsibility is to them, rather than
yourself.
Did God create the "evil"? If a god can take any
credit for the creation of this world and the good things that exist in
it, then it must also be accountable for the world it created and the evil
things in it. Just as we would hold accountable any human creator that
knowingly unleashes harm into the world.
Sunday, November 30, 2014
Saturday, May 3, 2014
Freewill, The illusion of
For every choice, there are perceived factuals which are weighed by
the chooser. Counter-factuals could alter the choice, depending on the
nature of the counter-factuals. The previous experience and current
psychological state (including desires) of the chooser are beyond their
choice. Fatuals that are not perceived do not weigh into the choice.
There is a choice that is made but under a given set of perceived
factuals and psychological state the chooser could not choose
differently. "I could if I wanted to." But you don't want to. That
would be a different psychological state.
For every choice I've ever made I can imagine circumstances which would have caused me to choose differently. Feeling how I felt, wanting what I wanted and knowing what I knew I could not have chosen differently. If there had been a different feeling, desire or understanding then the choice made would have been subject to those influences.
There are times when I don't know why I make the choices I do. But the spontaneous or capricious nature of the choice doesn't make my choice less deterministic. If anything these mysterious choices suggest that feeling and desire are capable of operating with minimal influence from an understanding of the circumstances.
When I do something random this does not suggest that I am exercising free will, rather I'm responding to (usually) ineffable stimuli. When I do something deliberate I am reacting to better identified, better considered stimuli. In all cases I am beholden to environmental, physiological and psychological influences.
Each feeling, desire and perception of circumstances is another bit of coercion steering me (and any of us) to a resulting choice. There may be no outside agent twisting our arm, the choices we make may be our own, but it is a mistake to think that for a given set of circumstances we are able to make more than one choice.
For every choice I've ever made I can imagine circumstances which would have caused me to choose differently. Feeling how I felt, wanting what I wanted and knowing what I knew I could not have chosen differently. If there had been a different feeling, desire or understanding then the choice made would have been subject to those influences.
There are times when I don't know why I make the choices I do. But the spontaneous or capricious nature of the choice doesn't make my choice less deterministic. If anything these mysterious choices suggest that feeling and desire are capable of operating with minimal influence from an understanding of the circumstances.
When I do something random this does not suggest that I am exercising free will, rather I'm responding to (usually) ineffable stimuli. When I do something deliberate I am reacting to better identified, better considered stimuli. In all cases I am beholden to environmental, physiological and psychological influences.
Each feeling, desire and perception of circumstances is another bit of coercion steering me (and any of us) to a resulting choice. There may be no outside agent twisting our arm, the choices we make may be our own, but it is a mistake to think that for a given set of circumstances we are able to make more than one choice.
Saturday, March 1, 2014
Morality
What is Morality and where does it come from?
It’s usually best to begin by defining confusable
terms. In this case I’m using “morality”
and “morals” to simply refer that part of us that seeks to act fairly, kindly
or altruistically. It is the innate
desire to do right. We may have rules,
laws, social conventions and other codified ethics. But the feeling, the underlying motive, the
meta-ethic is “morality.” This
definition may seem to be inconsistent with traditional usage. By this definition many activities
traditionally identified as immoral seem to be dismissed or perhaps still are immoral
but for different reasons.
In order for an entity to be a moral agent it must have
subjective experience and empathy.
The subjective experience is a matter of environmental
factors generating preferences in us.
Things that tend to damage us tend to feel uncomfortable or
painful. Things that tend to increase
our safety, survival and reproduction tend to feel comfortable or good. Without this subjective experience it would
be difficult to justify any claim of one thing or state being better than
another. We would still have
considerations of practicality. For
instance we might realize it is better to keep both arms than to lose one. Or we might consider it is better to be alive
than dead. But without subjectivity in
our experience we would not develop spontaneous preferences. Without our own subjective experience it
would be difficult to appreciate the subjective experience of others.
As biological organisms we have needs and constraints and as
a result: drives. Food, water and breathable
air cover our most basic individual needs.
Since we are mortal, we as a species need to reproduce as well. We require an environment that is neither too
hot nor too cold with a fairly narrow ideal temperature range. We can refer to Maslow’s Hierarchy for an
extend list of less basic needs. But the
required resources available to satisfy these needs (and/or our ability to
gather them) are limited. We typically
find ourselves in competition with each other and other organisms for the
resources to satisfy our needs.
We have the ability and tendency to recognize, anticipate
and appreciate the subjective experience of others. It’s difficult to say whether (or to what
degree) this empathy is genetic versus cultural (nature vs. nurture.) The physiology of mirror neurons supports
genetics but I wouldn’t expect that to be the whole story. Additionally we are social creatures. There are many species of social creatures
all of whom have little or no culture. Whether
empathy gave rise to our social drives or our social drives gave rise to our
empathy is subject to speculation. (“Empathy gave rise” is far more plausible.) But in humans social drive and empathy don’t
seem to scale in one-to-one correlation.
Subjectivity and empathy make us moral agents: entities
capable of recognizing, anticipating and appreciating the subjective experience
of other subjective entities, even where that capacity is not reciprocal. For
instance we would be able to appreciate the suffering of a komodo dragon but we
should not expect it to appreciate our suffering. The dragon is not a moral agent. What about a baboon or gorilla? These are creatures that appear to appreciate
the subjective states in others of their own kind, at least of their own
group. If they attacked a human they would
probably have a fair understanding of the suffering their human victim would
experience. But would they care, or
rather could they care? The answer seems
to rely on previous interaction, on established relationships and on the
situation at hand. Moral agency in
non-human primates appears to be present but stifled.
Group identity will strongly influence behavior in social
creatures. Our devotion to our many
social circles varies. Family tends to
generate the strongest devotion but shared experience and ideology can create
strong psychological bonds as well. We
find ourselves grouped with friends, neighbors, co-workers, civic groups,
political groups, people with shared interests (environment, sports team, music
genre/artists…), religious groups and others.
Our devotion to the people and groups we identify with can be based on
familiarity. But often we find ourselves
devoted to an ideal, a cultural concept, which in turn reinforces our devotion
to the related group and individuals.
From an evolutionary standpoint the power of cultural
influences may seem difficult to reconcile.
But ceremonies and rituals almost certainly predated language and served
to reinforce group cohesion. Behaviors that originally would have augmented kin
selection and nepotism have long since become just as effective at dissolving
family cohesion. I make this claim in
regards to potential rather than likelihood or necessity. Families may share ideological beliefs or
hold conflicting ideologies with varying degrees of dedication. In the early millennia of cultural
development it’s unlikely that there was any diversity. So evolutionarily, the strength of cultural
identity on group cohesion is not surprising.
In considering the origins of morality we should remember
that there are many social species aside from humans. Schools, hives, prides, packs, herds and
troops should make it immediately obvious that intelligence and culture are not
prerequisites to cooperation. Social
instinct has appeased natural selection in many species.
We tend to value individuals in our groups that contribute
more resources to the group. Conversely,
individuals that contribute less are generally devalued. And individuals who cheat jeopardize their
perceived status as a member of the group through a waning of trust. Our moral agency (subjective experience
combined with empathy) gives us perception of whether interactions are generous
or stingy, fair or unfair, kind or unkind, caring or callous, and generally
good or bad. We appreciate the
experience of the individual in a way we think of as rights. We appreciate our relationships and place in a
group in a way we think of as roles and responsibilities.
We need to execute some measure of selfishness to
survive. But given our limited ability
to gather necessary (and otherwise desirable) resources as lone individuals, we
also need some measure of selflessness, manifesting as cooperation. The underlying drives for each are instilled by
biology. Like most biological systems
the way things work, the ‘rules,’ tend to resemble self-balancing conditional
algorithms rather than linear instructions.
We seek equity for ourselves and others.
We deplore inequity at our expense and also when others suffer
unfairness. The more closely we identify
with others (an innate recognition of in-group status) the more sharply we
recognize and care about their suffering and well-being.
As cognitive social animals we share information:
culture. But cultural information is
highly subject to being incomplete, misleading or wrong (by degrees varying
form not quite right yet functional to completely contrary to demonstrable
factual reality.) And yet what we learn
from experience and from shared information influences how we perceive new
experience and information. We are entirely
capable of doing the wrong thing while thinking we are doing the right thing
based on existing beliefs. Ideologies
are particularly culpable but simple misunderstandings lead us astray as well. We develop beliefs which bias us when
considering new information which is added to our beliefs in cycles that allows
us to convince ourselves of just about anything.
As a result the idea of Objectivism (philosophical morality theory)
doesn’t quite make sense because it is based on subjective experience. Relativism doesn’t quite work because there
are some very basic, fundamental commonalities to the subjective experience,
many of which can be misinformed by cultural beliefs hijacking our
perception. Emotivism doesn’t work for
several reasons: we are always working with incomplete information, morality is
a social issue as much as (if not more than) a personal issue and again mistaken
beliefs can, perhaps must, skew our perception.
Tribalism presents another skew on morality. Our empathy for others and disdain of
injustice are stronger and consequently more motivating in-group, toward people
we identify with, than for “those other ones” (out-group). Us and them, worse us versus them, undermines
our ability and willingness to support “them.”
Ideologies, proximity, appearance, etc. create counter-productive us and them
barriers.
If there is any hope of anything resembling an objective
morality it will be accessible only by a willingness and ability to consider
our beliefs skeptically and strip away dubious opinions in order to find a
balancing mechanism that supports individual rights and social responsibility
based on common human subjective experience, empathy and a lust for fairness.
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)